The Pendulum Swings again: A Mathematical
Reassessment of Galileo’s Experiments with Inclined Planes
Alexander Hahn
1
, Notre Dame
Abstract. After over 300 years of scrutiny, the subject of Galileo continues to be
pursued with unabating intensity. Dava Sobel’s Galileo’s Daughter points to the
popular interest in the man and his legacy. The Catholic Church, understandably
interested in dispelling the notion that its censure of Galileo centuries ago is proof
positive that religious faith and science as well as ecclesiastical authority and free
pursuit of scholarship are irreconcilable, continues to offer explanations. New books,
articles and conferences probe both in breadth and in depth the magnetic field charged
by Galileo, science, and the Church.
Galileo’s analysis of the physics of motion has also received considerable atten-
tion. In particular, a great deal has been written during the past thirty years about
the structure and objectives of three experiments with inclined planes. Galileo had
carried them out in Padua and recorded them in his working papers. The assessments
of the three experiments differ widely in points of detail, but all regard them as so-
phisticated, ingenious, and remarkable. This article presents a new critical study of
these experiments. Its conclusion is that one of the experiments is indeed a success,
but that the other two fail and are abandoned because Galileo did not have a firm
enough grip on the underlying physical principles and mathematical relationships.
1. Galileo on Motion. Galileo’s journey of discovery of the laws of motion is
lengthy, twisted, and anything but smooth. We recall it only briefly. It is described
in [10], [11] and, in compelling detail, in [38].
Galileo’s early efforts in Pisa (1589-1592) to understand the phenomenon of motion
are the subject of the De motu manuscripts. Central to Galileo’s explanations are
two underlying concepts, a basic one of uniform specific speed of fall and the auxiliary
one of an impressed force, that account for the nonuniform motions actually observed.
The uniform specific speed of the object depends on the medium in which the object
moves and is determined - via Archimedean hydrostatics - by the difference in the
densities between object and medium. The impressed force is something that is put
into an object by an external mover. Once imparted, this impressed power decays
1
I wish to thank Ernan McMullin for much information about Galileo and his scientific pursuits,
and in particular for drawing my attention a number of years ago to the research of Stillman Drake
on Galileo’s working papers. Thanks also go to Noel Swerdlow for very useful insights, and to Neil
Delaney, David Kirkner, and Timothy O’Meara for many stimulating discussions about Galileo and
his work.
gradually and the speed of the body changes steadily until the impressed power is
completely dissipated and the object assumes its natural constant speed specific to
the medium in which the motion takes place. Galileo’s thinking during this time is
still heavily influenced by Aristotelian and medieval elements. Only towards the end
of the De motu does Galileo begin to accept the possibility that acceleration may be
a fundamental feature of fall.
During the Padua period (1597-1610) Galileo’s understanding of motion undergoes
transition. His 1604 letter to Fra Paolo Sarpi provides important testimony: ”the
spaces passed in natural motion are in proportion to the squares of the times taken,
and consequently that the spaces traversed in equal successive time intervals are to
the odd numbers ...” Diverted by his interests in astronomy and the well documented
conflict with the Church, Galileo does not present the final synthesis of his theory
of motion until 1638. The Discorsi [2] is the exposition of a learned, four day long
conversation among Salviati who represents Galileo himself, Sagredo an open minded
supporter of the new science, and Simplicio, an adherent of the old Aristotelian
point of view. Days three and four of these discussions focus in vernacular Italian
on the treatise De motu locali - a book within a book in scholarly Latin - that
is Galileo’s own systematic treatment of motion. It is intended to be a clear and
rigorous presentation in final form. Errors and missteps from earlier stages of Galileo’s
thinking are visible in the probing comments of the protagonists. The discussion
analyzes the motion of objects undergoing constant acceleration, both in the situation
of free fall and along inclined planes. Galileo derives his conclusions deductively,
often with geometric constructions. He expresses quantitative relationships between
time, distance, velocity, and acceleration, in terms of proportions; indeed, he uses
only proportions of magnitudes of the same kind, for example, distance to distance,
velocity to velocity, but not distance to time. In particular, he does not have the
real number system and decimal notation at his disposal and does not formulate his
conclusions in terms of equations involving variables and constants. (The systematic
development of all this was only in its infancy at this time.) Within his context,
Galileo arrives at the following basic insights.
1. All bodies falling in a vacuum do so with the same constant acceleration. For a
body falling from rest, the speed is proportional to the elapsed time. This is so both
in the situation of free fall and for balls rolling on an inclined plane.
2. The law of fall, namely, that the distance covered by a body moving from rest
(again, either in free fall or rolling on an inclined plane) is proportional to the square
of the time of the motion.
3. The trajectory of a projectile has parabolic shape.
2
Galileo regards two underlying principles as fundamental. One is a principle of
inertia, namely that a body moving with a certain constant velocity (speed and
direction) will continue to move with that same velocity unless an outside force acts
on it
2
. The second is a principle of superposition of motions, namely that projectile
motion can be conceptualized as an independent composite of a motion with constant
velocity and a vertical motion with constant acceleration. It must be emphasized that
Galileo’s basic concepts (for example, velocity and acceleration) lack the precision that
calculus would later give them and his principles of inertia and superposition never
reach a definitive and general state. See [5], [10] and [38] for instance.
2. Galileo’s Experiments. There is general agreement that Galileo arrived at his
conclusions by combining the thinking of predecessors, geometric deductions, thought
or ”arm chair” experiments, and actual ”hands on” experiments. However, the as-
sessments of the relative importance of these elements have changed over the years.
In particular, the question - central to an understanding of Galileo the physicist -
as to the quality and purpose of Galileo’s hands on experimentation has received a
diversity of answers.
Galileo’s contemporaries Descartes and Mersenne exercised skepticism about his
experiments. See [5, p. 107] and [8, p. 20]. For the most part, however, historians
have taken Galileo’s word for it (as expressed on the third day of the Discorsi ) that
he used carefully constructed experiments as an important tool of both discovery and
verification of his fundamental insights into motion. This includes Kant [3, preface]
and Mach [4]. This point of view prevailed until the late 1930’s when the influen-
tial historian Koyr´e proclaimed that Galileo’s real experiments were most certainly
inadequate and that he relied on thought experimentation. See [5, pp. 106-107]
and [6, p. 224]. The pendulum begins to swing back in 1961 when Settle [8] recon-
structed Galileo’s basic apparatus and demonstrated that Galileo could have carried
out with satisfactory precision the experiments with inclined planes he described.
While emphasizing the point that the progressive evolution of Galileo’s understand-
ing of motion must surely have had an experimental aspect, essays written as recently
as 1967 were still circumspect and tentative about the precise nature and impact of
these experiments. See [10, pp. 11-12] and [11, pp. 328-329]. The backward swing
of the pendulum gained speed instantly in the early 1970s when Drake [12] perused
Galileo’s unpublished working papers on motion in the Biblioteca Nazionale Centrale
2
It is important to note that in this article ”inertia” will be used to refer simply to a principle
of uniform motion and not to Newton’s definitive version of the concept. For Newton, inertia is
an inherent property of the mass of a body that causes it to resist any change in its state of rest
or motion along a straight line. This article parallels Galileo understanding of inertia as only a
kinematic principle or an assertion about the motion of an object under ideal conditions.
3
in Florence and found written records of Galileo’s experiments with inclined planes.
They are the ”smoking gun” that refutes the position of Koyr´e. These working papers
- there are 160 sheets or folios - are now bound as Volume 72, or Codex 72, of the
Galileo manuscripts. The websites
http://www.imss.fi.it/ms72/INDEX.HTM
or
http://www.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/Galileo
Prototype/index.htm
provide wonderful and very useful electronic renditions of the folios of the codex.
Many of the folios are drafts of theoretical discussions that would later appear in the
Discorsi. (The electronic version provides precise connections with cross-references.)
Many folios are filled with computations. A number of folios, 80r, 81r, 86a r, 87, 90r,
91v, 102, 107, 111, 113r, 114v, 115r, 116v, 117, 152r, and 175v among them, contain
diagrams and data that suggest studies of motion. The abbreviations r and v stand
for ”recto” and ”verso”, the ”front” and ”back” of the sheet in question. (In the
listing just given, if neither r nor v appears, then both sides of the sheet are relevant.)
Some of these folios are geometric explorations of the parabola and some are records
of experiments. The historians who have studied them consider it ”well substantiated
by the evidence” (watermarks, for example) that they stem from the later Paduan
period 1604-1610. For example, see Naylor [20, p. 366].
The present article will focus on 81r, 114v and 116v. Each of these folios gives
evidence of an experiment in which Galileo has placed an inclined plane on a table,
lets a ball roll down the plane, and records quantitative data about the ball’s flight
from the table’s edge to the ground. Salviati informs us on the third day of the
Discorsi that Galieo repeated some of his experiments ”a full hundred times.” Thus
it would seem that each recorded measurement represents a cluster of trials. The
general conclusions of Drake [12, 27, 32, 36, 37], Drake-MacLachlan [16], Naylor [13,
18, 19, 20, 25, 26, 28], and Hill [33, 35] - these are the historians who have studied
them most thoroughly - are in agreement:
Drake [32, p. 4] uses folios 81r and 114v to conclude that Galileo is a ”skilled
experimentalist capable of holding his results within a variance of four units ...” The
unit referred to here is Galileo’s punto, or ”point”, a unit of length slightly less than
one millimeter.
Naylor [18, pp. 168-169], reflecting about 81r, speaks of ”indications that Galileo
carried out meticulous, thorough-going studies of the form of projectile motion” and
suggests that ”Galileo had a striking talent for combining a mathematical approach
4
to nature with a considerable mathematical technique. The simplicity and power of
this particular form of experiment is quite remarkable.”
Hill [35, p. 666] comments that ”worksheets 81r, 114v, and 116v reveal an impres-
sive experimental program, ingenious in structure, ambitious in concept, eminently
successful in execution. This series of procedures enabled Galileo to provide powerful,
perhaps empirically decisive, evidence for both the new speed law and the parabolic
trajectory.”
It is a fact that Galileo’s record of the experiments on these folios omits impor-
tant details, in reference to both the descriptive and numerical elements. Thus, an
important ingredient in the studies of these folios has been the careful reconstruction
of the experiments from the information that Galileo does supply. These reconstruc-
tions - both actual and mathematical - become an important part of the evidence.
The numerical data that they generate is carefully compared with the analogous data
from Galileo’s record. These comparisons are used to inform the authors’ comments
about the plausibility of their reconstructions and the validity of their analyses of
the experiments. Unfortunately, in terms of particulars (for example, the inclination
of the inclined plane and release heights of the balls), these reconstructions as well
as the conclusions drawn from them - specifically the purpose and precision of the
experiments - differ widely.
This state of affairs calls for a sober re-examination of these folios. What aspects
of his insights about motion did Galileo put to the test? How precise were his experi-
ments? What conclusions can legitimately and compellingly be drawn from Galileo’s
record of them? Is there indeed convincing evidence that they were successful? The
answer to these questions is the purpose of the discussion that follows. The focus
will be on the folios themselves (rather than the reconstruction of the experiments)
and on related aspects of the Discorsi. The folios 116v, 81r, and 114v and all the
information on them are reproduced below. The originals can be studied at either of
the websites listed above. The organization of the calculations on 116v and 114v into
rectangular ”frames” follows the practice of the websites.
3. The Experiment of Folio 116v. The statement punti 828 altezza della tavola
tells us that Galileo recorded distances in units he calls punti (that is to say ”points”)
and that he had a table 828 punti high. There is agreement among the historians
already mentioned (based on evidence from folio 166r) that one punto is equal to
approximately 0.94 millimeters. The diagram together with the computations on
the folio confirm that he placed an inclined plane on the table, fixed an angle of
inclination, and released a ball (likely of bronze) from the respective heights h of
300, 600, 800, 828, and 1000
5
punti above the horizontal table top. Galileo might have made use of a curved de-
flector to provide a smooth transition for the ball from the inclined plane to the
horizontal table. His sketch on folio 175v shows that he considered such deflectors.
After a short run on the table, the ball flew off to land on a horizontal floor. Galileo
measured the respective distances from the point of impact of the ball to the base of
300
600
800
828
1000
300 . 800
800
2 1 3 3
6 4 0 0 0 0
2 1 3 3
800
1 3 0 6
1 7 0 6 4 0 0
1
2 3
260
1
300
2 2 0 8
300 . 828
800
2 2 0 8
6 6 2 4 0 0
800
1 3 2 9
1 7 6 6 4 0 0
1
2 3
300 . 1000
800
2 6 6 6
8 0 0 0 0 0
300
7
2 4 0
1
8001172
1328
1340
1500
doveria 1460
dria 41
doveria esser 1306
doveria per rispondere al primo esser 1131
punti 828 altezza della tavola
doveria 1330
2 6 6 7
8 0 0
1 4 6 0
2133600
1
24
1 1 3 1
1600
800
1280000
1
2 1
2 2 3
731
C06
C07
C09
C01
1 4 3 0 6 2
6.2
2.2
1
1640
820
1344800
1 1 5
32800
1312
80
30 . 60
160 0
480 0
30
80
30 . 80
300 640000
2 1 3
1394
1603
1866
236
247
59
2 1
2 2 5
1
286
1 3 7
262
264
2920
1
17
20
C08
C10
C11
C12
1 6 1 6 0 4
2 8 4 9 0 0
C03
C02
C05
C04
dria 10
dria 22
dria 40
Folio 116v (size of original: 306 by 207 mm)
6
the table (the point directly below the start of the ball’s flight) and recorded these
on the folio as
(a) 800, 1172, 1328, 1340, and 1500
punti. These are the experimental values that correspond to the various heights of
release listed above.
3A. Understanding the Folio. We now turn to the analysis of the experiment
as well as the computations that Galileo carried out. Consider the ball in its initial
position on the inclined plane. Let
h = the height of the ball above the table, and
d = the distance from the ball to the bottom of the inclined plane.
Now release the ball and let
t = the time it takes for the ball to descend to the bottom of the plane,
v = the speed of the ball at time t. This is also the speed of the ball at
the beginning of its fall from the table. Finally, let
R = the distance from the point of impact of the ball to the point on the
ground precisely below the starting point of the ball’s flight.
At the time of the experiment - before the end of the Paduan period in 1610 -
Galileo had discovered, or at least wrestled with, all essential aspects of his program
on motion as outlined in Section 1 above. In particular, he was in a position to put
to the test the proportion
(i) v t
as well as the square law
(ii) d t
2
(deduced from (i) in Proposition II. Theorem II of the Discorsi). From his principle
of inertia he could assume that the horizontal component of the velocity is constant
throughout the ball’s flight and hence equal to v. (Given the relatively small velocities,
distances and times, Galileo could safely assume that air resistance would not play a
significant role. See [19, p. 408].) In reference to the vertical component of the ball’s
flight, Galileo knew that the time of fall of the horizontally projected ball from the
7
table to the ground is independent of its starting velocity v. So this time is equal to
the time t
0
that it takes for a ball to fall vertically from rest through the height of the
table. Notice that these observations rely on the principle of superposition. Galileo
can conclude that
(iii) R v
with t
0
the constant of proportionality. By similar triangles (the angle of inclination
of the inclined plane is fixed) h d. After putting the above proportions together,
Galileo has
(iv) h d t
2
v
2
R
2
.
Therefore, R
2
h. So, if releases of the ball at the heights of h
0
and h above the
table result in points of impact at the respective distances of R
0
and R from the foot
of the table, then
(v)
R
2
R
2
0
=
h
h
0
.
It is this relationship that the experiment recorded on folio 116v is designed to con-
firm. Galileo’s next step is to insert the values h
0
= 300 and R
0
= 800 from the
experiment. By doing so, he in effect determines, or at least approximates, the con-
stants of proportionality that link R
2
and h, or equivalently, R and
h. The equation
(vi) R =
800
300
h.
captures what he does. It remains for Galileo to compute R for h successively equal to
600, 800, 828, and 1000, and to compare the resulting values with the measurements
for R that were provided - see (a) - by the experiment. The successive values for R
that Galileo computes are (in punti)
(b) , 1131, 1306, 1330, and 1460.
The refers to the value R = 800 that was used along with the corresponding
h = 300 to obtain (vi).
Galileo records these numbers on the folio with the phrase doveria esser (or simply
doveria) meaning ”ought to be.” He also includes his calculations. For example,
the calculation for h = 600 is carried out in frame C01. Galileo first computes
R
2
=
800·800·600
300
= 1600 · 800 = 1280000 and calculates R =
1280000 = 1131.
For h = 800, this is done in C06. For h = 1000, the computation can be seen in
8
frames C09 and C08. In C09, Galileo computes 1000 ×800 = 800000 and divides this
result by 300 to get 2666. In C08, he multiplies the more accurate value 2667 of this
computation (the actual value is 2666
2
3
) by 800 to get 2133600. This is R
2
.TogetR,
he calculates
2133600 = 1460. The computation in frame C10 is analogous to that
of C01 and suggests that Galileo also considered a table height of 820 punti. Note
that some of the computations are only approximations and that the computation
1344800 = 115 in frame C10 is incomplete. In the course of computing the square
root of a number, Galileo crosses the digits of the number out. In the rendition of
the folio above these numbers are entered in a lighter shade.
Galileo compares his experimental values (a) to his theoretical values (b) and
records the respective differences of 41, 22, 10, and 40 punti using the abbreviation
dria for differentia. The fact that the theoretical values fall short of the experimental
values (from about 1 to 4 centimeters) seems contrary to expectation. After all,
the experimental values are subject to the retarding effects of the imperfections in
Galileo’s experimental setup, whereas the theoretical values are not. The explanation
is provided by the fact that Galileo’s theory, as captured by equation (vi), depends
on one data point from the experiment. We will see, in particular, that the measured
distance of 800 punti (corresponding to the height of 300 punti) falls short of the
predicted mark. So the constant
800
300
is too small, and thus all of Galileo’s computed
values are too small as well.
We turn next to the question of the precision of the experiment of folio 116v.
We will test the accuracy of the experimental values (a) against the predictions of
elementary mechanics. (Galileo’s theory can’t be used because it depends on his
experiment.) We will only outline these matters here. The details are available in
many texts, for example, in Chapter 9.3 of the basic calculus text [42]
3
. Note that
the analysis that follows goes far beyond what Galileo was familiar with.
3B. The Underlying Mathematics. Return to the ball on the inclined plane and
assume that the ball is homogeneous. Let t = 0 be the instant at which it is released.
For any time t 0, let f(t) be the frictional force on the rolling ball (a priori it
depends on t). This is the force that rotates the ball. Assume that there is neither
slippage (as the ball would experience on a frictionless surface) nor any additional
retardation of the motion down the plane (as would be the case if the surface were
”bumpy” or ”sticky”). The connection between the torque produced by the frictional
force, the resulting angular acceleration of the ball, and the ball’s index of inertia (this
connection is provided by the rotational analogue of force = mass × acceleration),
3
My interest in the experiments of Galileo had its beginning in my efforts to develop applications
of calculus with interesting historical connections for this book.
9
leads to the equation
f(t)=
2
5
ma(t)
where m is the mass of the ball and a(t) is its linear acceleration down the plane. By
Newton’s second law and the fact that the component of gravity down the plane is
F = mg sin β, where β is the angle of inclination of the plane, we get
ma(t)=F f(t)=mg sin β
2
5
ma(t) ,
and therefore,
a(t)=
5g
7
sin β.
This informs us in turn that the velocity of the ball at the bottom of the plane is
v =
10
7
gh. (Alternatively, this equation can be established by using the law of
conservation of energy. See [17, pp. 398-399].) Combining this with one of the basic
equations of projectile motion and letting y
0
be the height of the table, provides the
connection
R =2
5
7
y
0
h
between the starting height h and the distance R from the point of impact of the ball
to the foot of the table. With the substitution y
0
= 828 this equation becomes
(vii) R =2
5
7
828
h.
Plugging Galileo’s starting heights of 300, 600, 800, 828, and 1000 into equation
(vii) for h, we get the values (again in punti)
(c) 842, 1191, 1376, 1400, and 1538
for the corresponding distances R.
This model applies to the ideal situation: a perfectly round and homogeneous
ball; a path that is perfectly smooth and flat with no tilts other than the inclination
of the plane; a force of friction that rotates the ball without slippage but provides
no additional impedance; and a deflector that provides a perfectly smooth transition
from the plane to the table. In addition, to conform to the situation of the model, the
10
table as well as the floor on which the ball impacts need to be perfectly horizontal.
There is, of course, no such perfection in the context of Galileo’s experimental setup.
In sum, the expectation is that the ball will land short of its theoretical target. A
comparison of the lists of numbers (a) and (c) confirms this. We know, of course,
from the discussion on the third day of the Discorsi, that Galileo is fully aware that his
fundamental laws of motion apply only in idealized situations and that any experiment
or ”real” situation will encounter ”impediments.” Notice that the ”bottom lines” of
the analyses of Sections 3A and 3B, namely the equations (vi) and (vii), differ only
in the value of the constant, and that
800
300
46.19 falls short of the correct value
2
5
7
· 828 48.64.
So far we have said nothing about the groove that guides the ball down the plane.
The description of an inclined plane experiment in the Discorsi [2, Crew-Salvio p. 171,
compare Drake p. 169] informs us that there was a channel ”a little more than one
finger in breadth” cut into the inclined plane, and that ”having made this groove very
straight, smooth, and polished, and having lined it with parchment, also as smooth
and polished as possible, we rolled along it a hard, smooth, bronze ball ...” The
fact that Galileo says nothing specific about the groove presents a problem, because
different configurations of the cross-section require different theoretical explanations.
We now let d be the diameter of the ball and consider the most likely possibilities.
If the cross-section of the groove is a circular arc of radius greater than the radius
d
2
of the ball, then in the ideal situation, the ball will roll on the bottom of the groove
throughout its descent. This is a situation to which the mathematical model already
described applies. Asssume next that the groove has rectangular cross-section and let
w>0 be its width. If d w, then the ball is supported by the bottom of the groove
and rolls entirely within the groove. Again, the model already described applies. But
if d>wand the groove is deep enough, then the rolling ball does not touch the
bottom of the groove and is instead supported by its two edges. In this case, the
dynamics are different. The mathematical model of this situation (obtained by an
analysis similar to that above) provides the relationship
(viii) R =2
y
0
1+
2
5
·
d
2
d
2
w
2
h.
This equation also applies to a groove with a cross-section in the shape of an isosceles
triangle, if w is taken to be the distance between the two points of contact of the ball
with the groove. Let y
0
= 828 punti be the height of the table. Because
d
2
d
2
w
2
> 1,
the value of equation (viii) is less than the value of equation (vii) for any h>0. In
particular, the values for R that equation (viii) supplies for the respective starting
11
heights h equal to 300, 600, 800, 828, and 1000 are less than the values (c) supplied by
equation (vii). Hence the values provided by equation (viii) will be closer to Galileo’s
experimental values (a).
Now to the comparison of Galileo’s experimental data against the predictions
of the theory. It follows from the analysis of the cross-section of the groove that
the respective differences between the experimental data (a) and the predictions
(c) are the largest possible. Therefore, in assessing the accuracy of the folio 116v
experiment, these differences provide the worse case scenario. The differences are
42 = 800 842, 19 = 1172 1191, 48 = 1328 1376, 60 = 1340 1400 and
38 = 1500 1538 punti. In terms of percentages, this amounts to 5.0%, 1.6%,
3.5%, 4.3%, and 2.5%, respectively. What can be said about this discrepancy?
While the inclined planes used by Galileo seem no longer to exist, we do know - see
[34] for example - that the apparatus that Galileo used in other investigations was well
crafted. The physicists Shea and Wolf [17], considering the many sources of possible
experimental error in the folio 116v experiment, regard the data generated by Galileo
to fall ”within acceptable limits of experimental error.” All indications are that this
assessment is correct. For example, Naylor [13, pp. 109-111] reconstructed the folio
116v experiment with considerable care (the cross-section of the groove was a circular
arc of radius greater than
d
2
) and obtained distance data very close to Galileo’s.
4. The Experiment of Folio 81r. There is a consensus among historians - see [18],
[35], and [37, Chapter 8] - that folio 81r focusses its attention on the trajectories of
balls that are propelled obliquely into space after having descended down an inclined
plane placed on a table. In important contrast to folio 116v, the balls drop directly
from the inclined plane and there is no horizontal deflection. Each of the three
curves on the folio corresponds to a certain fixed angle of inclination of the plane
and fixed starting height of the ball. In repeated trials Galileo intercepts the flight
of the ball with horizontal planes placed at different heights and marks the points
of impact. Evidently, he starts by placing the intercepting plane at a distance of
53+53+77
1
2
+146 = 329
1
2
punti below the plane of the table and ”calibrates” the three
trajectories so that the the points of impact are at the respective horizontal distances
of 250, 250 + 250 = 500, and 250 + 250 + 250 = 750 punti from the table. He then
successively raises the intercepting plane as indicated and measures the horizontal
distances of the points of impact of the ball for each of the three trajectories. The
Latin phrase on the folio informs us that these vertical and horizontal distances are
given in the same scale. Galileo, interested in the shape of the three curves, has in
effect provided five sets of coordinates for each of them.
Observe that other than the diagram, the folio contains only three small clusters of
12
numbers (some of which are related to those of the diagram). One of these considers
a group of four numbers and divides each by 4. However, there is nothing to suggest a
successfully completed experiment. Nor does Codex 72 appear to contain folios with
computations that inform 81r. Before jumping to conclusions, however, it is necessary
to look at 81r in the light of the relevant context. We know that Galileo regarded the
verification of the parabolic law as a primary goal of his studies on motion. During
Altitudines in ab mensuratae sunt
cum scala maiorum transversalium bc
250 - 250
170 - 177
1/
2
121 - 1301/2
81 -
53
a
b
c
53
81
121
87
1/2
1301/2
250
89
146
77
1/2
178
131
250
250
170
177
1/2
185
131
88
37
200 . 86
50 21 23
250
141
46
32
22
9
1
4
3
4
1
2
1
4
1
2
1
4
Folio 81r (size of original: 304 by 205 mm)
13
the Paduan period he invested considerable effort towards this end. See [14, p. 336]
and [38, pp. 205-213] for instance. Given this, one would have to believe that Galileo
designed the experiment of folio 81r - at least in significant part - to test the parabolic
hypothesis, and that he would have regarded the experiment a success only if it
provided solid evidence for or against it. Let’s consider what Galileo was up against.
The diagram below abstracts the essence of what is happening. It shows the path of
the ball down the inclined plane from right to left to the edge of the inclined plane
at the point O. Thereafter, the ball is in flight and is shown in typical position B.
The plane determined by the incline and the horizontal plane of the table top are
denoted (both in cross section) by P and H. The line V is the vertical through O.
The distance from B to the line V is denoted by x and that from B to H by y. The
x
y
x
i
D
D
a
i
D
V
O
B
P
H
question facing Galileo for each of the three curves is this. Are the pairs x and y that
he singles out in the diagram of the folio in a relationship that is parabolic, or at least
14
close to parabolic?
Let’s analyze the matter in Galileo’s terms. The principle of superposition of
motion tells us that the motion of the ball from O to its typical position B is the
composite of an inertial component along P and a uniformly accelerated component
down to B. These components result in the vertical displacements D
i
and D
a
re-
spectively. The distance D
i
can be obtained by measuring up to the inclined plane
from the table top at a distance of x units from O. Notice that D
i
= c
i
x where c
i
is the slope of the inclined plane. What about D
a
? Let t be the elapsed time of the
motion of the ball from O to B. The proportion x t is a consequence of the inertial
motion. So t
2
x
2
. By considering the downward accelerated motion, D
a
x
2
.
Galileo could have approximated the corresponding constant of proportionality c
a
`a
la 116v by using D
a
= y D
i
and the first data point (x =81,y = 53 for the inner
curve). Since he knew the basics about parabolas, it would remain for him to test
whether the pairs of distances x and y that he has recorded satisfy the equation
y = D
a
+ D
i
= c
a
x
2
+ c
i
x
in an approximate way.
Why doesn’t Galileo carry this out on folio 81r? Unlike Fermat and his famous
margin, he had more than room enough (on the bottom half of the page and the
empty reverse side). Or on a separate folio? Or elsewhere? The short answer is that
he was not able to do so. Why not?
We have just seen that a meaningful assessment of the data of 81r relies on the
principles of superposition and inertia. The principle of superposition isolates from
the ball’s flight a component of motion along the non-horizontal line P and it is this
non-horizontal motion to which the principle of inertia is applied. The fact is, however,
that Galileo neither formulated nor used the principles of inertia and superposition
at this level of generality. The studies [5, pp. 186-187], [10, pp. 27-31], and [38, pp.
225-226] support this point. For example, on the first day of the Dialogo [1] - its
publication in 1632 occurs more than twenty years after the experiment of folio 81r -
Sagredo tells us:
”In the horizontal plane no velocity whatever would ever be naturally
acquired, sice the body in this position will never move. But motion in
a horizontal line which is tilted neither up nor down is circular motion
about the center; therefore circular motion is never acquired naturally
without straight motion to precede it; but being once acquired, it will
continue perpetually with uniform velocity.”
15
Early on the fourth day of the Discorsi (published in 1638), the principles of inertia
and superposition are discussed only in the context of a motion that is the composite
of a horizontal motion of constant speed and a vertical motion that is accelerated.
Galileo then uses them to provide a proof of the parabolic law in the case of horizontal
projection. But he presents no such proof in the oblique case. There is convincing
evidence that Galileo’s protracted efforts to come to grips with the obliquely projected
trajectory - the gunner’s problem - were unsuccessful. The analysis in [38, pp. 205-
213, 225-226, 241-243, 251-258, 262-264] draws this conclusion from a careful study
of both the Discorsi and the relevant theoretical studies in the folios of Codex 72.
Indeed, when the proof in the oblique case is supplied by Cavalieri in 1632, Galileo
reacts with dismay in a letter (see [7, p. 75] or [10, p. 23]) written in the same year
to his frequent correspondent Cesare Marsili:
”I cannot hide from your most excellent Lordship that the information
scarcely pleased me, seeing that the first fruits of more that forty years’
study, of which I had revealed a large part in close confidence to the
said Father, were to be taken away from me, and I was to be deprived
of that glory that I desired so ardently and that I was promising myself
after such long efforts; for really my first intention, that which incited
me to meditate upon motion, had been to find that line, and though
I succeeded in demonstrating it, I know how much trouble I had in
arriving at that conclusion.”
The proof of the parabolic ”line” that ”said Father” Cavalieri and later Torricelli in
1644 provide are based on the more general principles of inertia and superposition.
See [5, pp. 236-244] and [38, pp. 274-276]. They are the same as those used in the
analysis of 81r presented above. In spite of Galileo’s assertion that he succeeded, the
demonstration he refers to does not appear in any of his published works, letters, or
manuscripts. The empty bottom half of folio 81r (as well as the empty reverse side) is
a concrete example of this gap. Galileo was unable to exploit the promising diagram
and abandoned this early effort to analyze the trajectory of an obliquely projected
ball.
However, the diagram does provide information about the accuracy with which
Galileo observed and measured the trajectories. Return to the previous figure and
take the lines H and V to be the x and y axes of a standard coordinate system
with the punto as the unit of length. Because the horizontal and vertical distances
travelled by the balls were small, their speeds were small as well. So we will assume
that air resistance was negligible, and that the trajectories that Galileo observed were
precise parabolas. In terms of the coordinate system, each parabola is given by an
16
equation of the form y = ax
2
+ bx, where a is a positive constant, b is non-negative,
and x 0. The line of the sloping plane P has equation y = bx and ax
2
measures the
vertical deviation of the motion of the ball from this line. (This parallels the earlier
analysis of folio 81r.) Let’s turn to the inner trajectory. In reference to the coordinate
system, Galileo’s data points are
(81, 53), (121, 106), (170, 183.5), (250, 329.5) .
The parabola of the form y = ax
2
+ bx that fits these data points best - in the sense
of least squares - is
() y = 0.00351906 x
2
+0.446797 x.
(Any of several software packages - in the present case Mathematica - can be used to
supply this equation.) If Galileo’s cluster of data points were to fall on a parabola
precisely, then () would be that parabola. Therefore, an assessment of the extent
to which they do not gives insight into the accuracy of Galileo’s measurements. The
x-coordinates of the points on parabola () whose y-coordinates correspond to
53, 106, 183.5, and 329.5
are 74.7, 121.4, 173.5, and 249.0, respectively. When comparing these numbers
with the horizontal distances that the folio records for the inner curve, we see that
the difference 81 74.7=6.3 is the largest. The indication is that at least some
of the measurements deviate from the reality that Galileo observes by more than
6 punti. Similar analyses of the middle and outer curves provide inaccuracies in
excess of 9 and 12 punti. Inaccuracies of this size are hardly surprising considering
what is involved. Galileo has to set the intercepting planes perfectly horizontally
at the vertical distances of 53, 106=53+53, 183.5 = 53+53+77.5 and 329.5=
53+53+77.5 + 146 punti below the plane of the table, locate with precision the
points of impact of the ball, and measure the distances from these points to the table.
This analysis applies only to distance measurements involving the trajectory. In
the context of folio 116v, there will be additional inaccuracies having to do with the
inclined plane, the groove, and the ball. In particular, we can safely conclude that
the experimental inaccuracies will be much greater than 6 punti in each of the trials
of the folio 116v experiment. The claim by Drake that Galileo experimented ”within
a variance of four units” is therefore not sustainable.
5. The Experiment of Folio 114v. There is general agreement that the sketch
on folio 114v also depicts the trajectories of a ball that had rolled down an inclined
17
plane placed on a table. The angle of inclination is fixed, the ball rolls down from
various heights, and the numbers
253, 337, 395, 451, 495, 534, and 573
are the recorded distances (in punti) of the corresponding points of impact of the ball
from the foot of the table. In contrast to 116v, there is no information about the
116
928
200
580
58
6728
8 2
141
116
200 .
846
141
141
1 6 3 5 6
8 1
59
78
472
413
4602
141
32
37
37
259
111
1369
1089
784
3242
5 6
33
33
9 9
9 9
1 0 8 9
28
28
784
18868
1 5 5
1 3 7
24135
70
70
69
69
621
404
4661
4900
4812
3925
6 2
9 1
135
193
3
2
253 337 395 451 495 534 573
1 4 1 . 5 9
2 0 0 . 1 4 1
7 8 . 2 6
8
16
20000
3
1 4 1
1 6 4
2 4
1
2 8
. . . . .
. . . . .
26
700
5
32
32
624
. . . . .
. . . . .
7
122
8417
6
1
9
335
181
63
. . . . .
1
23
267
19 9
1 0 8
1
25
305
1 6
1 10
C02
C03
C04
C05
C06
C07
C08
C09
C10
C12
C11
C01
Folio 114v (size of original: 285 by 202 mm)
18
starting heights of the ball. Nor is there any information about the initial direction
of the motion (because the angle of inclination of the plane is not supplied).
What information do Galileo’s calculations provide about the experiment? Frame
C01 computes 116 · 58 = 6728 and then
6728 = 82. Frame C02 calculates
141·116
200
=
81. Frame C03 shows only a fragment of a multiplication. (The top right corner of
the folio is missing). Frame C04 carries out
20000 = 141. Frame C05 computes
59·78
141
= 32 and lists two pairs of numbers. Frame C07 shows that the squares of 33
and 28 are 1089 and 784 respectively. Frame C06 shows the square of 37 to be 1369,
shows that the sum of 1369, 1089 and 784 is 3242, and calculates the square root of
this number as 56. Frames C08 and C10 compute
24135 = 155 and
18868 = 137.
Frame C09 computes the squares of 70 and 69 to be 4900 and 4661 respectively and
lists the number 4812. Frame C11 calculates
3925 as 62 and lists the more accurate
value 63. Frame C12, finally, computes
8417 = 91 and seems to point out that
135
193
is
approximately
2
3
. Note that some of these computations provide only approximations
and that 69
2
= 4761 (and not 4661). The study of these computations does not reveal
any apparent connections with the diagram on the folio and the sequence of distances
that are recorded on it. (Nor are such connections provided in previous studies of
folio 114v.) In particular, there appears to be no evidence on the folio that suggests
a successful experiment.
What might the purpose of 114v have been? The diagram on the folio shows that
the trajectories are oblique. Because the three folios under study were crafted at
about the same time, it seems reasonable to suppose that Galileo intended to pursue
for oblique projection what he had accomplished on 116v for horizontal projection.
So he might have attempted (perhaps among other things) to establish a relationship
between the distances R = 253, 337, 395, 451, 495, 534, and 573 of the points of impact
of the ball from the foot of the table and the other relevant parameters: the height
y
0
of the table, the angle of inclination φ
0
of the plane, and the heights h from which
the ball was released.
Let’s have a look at the relationship between these parameters that a current
mathematical model provides. Inserting the speed v =
10
7
gh that the ball has at
the bottom of the plane (see Section 3B) into the standard equation for the range of
a projectile, shows that
R =
5
7
h sin(2φ
0
)+
5
2
7
2
h
2
sin
2
(2φ
0
)+
20
7
hy
0
cos
2
φ
0
.
The most simple special case of this equation (other than the case φ
0
= 0 that 116v
considers) is φ
0
= sin
1
(
1
2
)=30
which Galileo could have achieved simply by raising
the end of the plane a distance of one half its length above the table top. In this case,
19
sin 2φ
0
= cos φ
0
=
3
2
and the equation simplifies to
R =
5
14
3 h +
3
2
5
2
7
2
h
2
+
20
7
hy
0
=
5
14
3 h +
3
2
5
7
h
5
7
h +4y
0
.
Finally, taking y
0
= 53+53+77.5 + 146 = 329.5 from folio 81r (as [35] plausibly
suggests), we get
R =
5
14
3 h +
3
2
5
7
h
5
7
h + 1318 .
It is most unlikely that Galileo - working with proportions - could have made much
headway in the direction of understanding the relationship between h and R even in
this simple situation. Only algebraic equations arising from analytic geometry could
have provided the necessary insights.
Therefore, as the examination of the folio itself already suggests, Galileo’s diagram
is the residue of an inconclusive and abandoned experiment and his calculations served
a later and different purpose. Naylor [19, p. 403] observed long ago that the diagram
on the folio is unrelated to the calculations, but concluded instead that the latter
must be lost.
6. Previous Assessments of the Folios. It was argued in Sections 4 and 5 that
the experiments whose footprints are visible on folios 81r and 114v failed and that
Galileo abandoned them. The experiment of 81r failed because Galileo did not have
a broad enough grasp on the principles of inertia and superposition, and that of
114v was not successful because the relationships between the numerical parameters
of the experiment were beyond his understanding. But how is it that accomplished
historians are able to conclude that these experiments were significant achievements?
And what are their arguments?
Drake agrees that the experiments recorded on the two folios did not succeed, but
does not leave it at that and says ([37, p. 124]):
”Without analytic geometry, he lacked the mathematical tools for suc-
cess, which is why he never mentioned the investigations. It is precisely
because they did not succeed that they are of great interest, for they
show how Galileo went about attacking a physical problem when it lay
beyond his powers of solution.”
He then goes on to provide very specific details about Galileo’s experimental setup
about which Galileo himself was completely silent. See [32, p. 4] and [37, pp. 124-
127]:
20
”Analysis of Galileo’s measurements of downward oblique projections,
on ff. 114v and 81r, made it possible to describe in fair detail the
apparatus and procedures he had used. His inclined plane was grooved
to guide the ball, as decribed in Two New Sciences [i.e., the Discorsi],
width of groove 8
1
2
punti being such as to reduce the linear acceleration
by 5.75%, the ball used being of radius 10 punti. For f. 114v the angle
of the plane was set so that horizontal advance was double the vertical
descent; that is, at tan
1
1
2
or 26
.565. For f. 81r, the angles where
sin
1
1
3
,
1
6
, and
1
12
. Galileo’s measurements of projections on both doc-
uments were accurate within 4 punti.”
How does Drake arrive at this? He reconstructs the experiments of the folios from
the fragments that Galileo provides. When a reconstruction provides data that are
in tight agreement with the recorded measurements of the folio, Drake regards both
the reconstruction and the conclusions drawn from it as the likely explanations of
Galileo’s procedures. In light of his analysis of folios 114v and 81r, Drake revises his
earlier assessment of folio 116v. See [32, pp. 4-5] and [37, pp. 110-113]:
”This information, gleaned over a period of years, made it no longer
tenable to suppose that on f. 116v Galileo had measured incorrectly
by as much as 40 punti, as seemed to be implied by calculations of
his own on that page. A skilled experimentalist capable of holding his
results within a variance of four units would not err by ten times that
amount in two out of five recorded measurements. Accordingly, I have
re-examined f. 116v ...
Whereas his earlier conclusions rely on actual reconstructions of the experiments,
his re-examination of 116v turns to theory. In particular, Drake selects the mathemat-
ical model of equation (viii) of Section 3B. His choices d = 20 punti for the diameter
of the ball and w =8.5 punti for the width of the rectangular groove ”slow down” the
theory, but not enough to bring the predictions to within 4 punti of Galileo’s experi-
ment. To accomplish this, Drake argues that the height of Galileo’s table must have
been y
0
= 800 for some trials of the experiment and y
0
= 820 for the others, instead
of the 828 punti that the folio specifies. Refer to [32, pp. 5-13] and [37, Chapter 7].
That Drake’s strategy of reconstruction is fundamentally flawed is demonstrated
by the other analyses of folios 81r and 114v. Their authors produce different recon-
structions that also generate data that is in close agreement with Galileo’s fragmen-
tary record. However, the insights about the experiments that are derived from them
deviate substantially from those of Drake.
21
Even though a comparison of the diagrams of 114v and 116v suggests the contrary,
Naylor infers from his reconstruction that folio 114v is an experiment about horizontal
projection rather than oblique projection. He thinks that the experiment covers the
same territory as 116v and considers it a success. In reference to Drake’s analysis he
says ([13, p. 115]):
”The view that Galileo would roll spheres down an incline, compile a
list of observations, and then realize his total inability to interpret the
information, certainly seems a little out of character.”
Naylor regards the experiment of 81r to have been a successful test of the parabolic
trajectory. In [18, p. 167] he argues that
”... there are good grounds for believing that Galileo suspected that
the curve of the projectile trajectory could well be a parabola. If this
was the case, then his knowledge of the parabola would enable him to
design his experiment in such a way as to test this hypothesis. His
experiment suggests that it was designed on the basis of knowledge of
certain relatively simple yet unique properties of parabolas having a
common axis.”
In Naylor’s version of Galileo’s experiment the three parabolic trajectories are com-
pared not only under the assumption that all three parabolas have the same axis
but that they also have the same apex. But is this assumption consistent with the
data on the folio? The same least squares approximation that produced the equation
y =0.446797 x 0.00351906 x
2
for the inner trajectory (see Section 4) provides the
equations y =0.177481 x 0.00097007 x
2
for the middle trajectory and the equation
y =0.10604 x 0.000447278 x
2
for the outer trajectory. Elementary calculus tells us
that the axes of these parabolas cross the x-axis near x =63,x =91, and x = 119,
respectively. Therefore, the axis of the parabola that fits the inner data best is 56
punti from the axis of the parabola that fits the outer data best. In the context of the
distances recorded on folio 81r, this is excessive. In other words, there is no indication
that the experiment of folio 81r deals with parabolas that have a common axis.
Hill [35] also makes use of reconstructions. He considers 114v and 81r to be
connected and argues in [35, p. 661] that 114v provisionally, but effectively, tests
whether the speed of the ball in its descent (from rest) down the inclined plane is
proportional to the square root of the distance that it covers. He finds his data to
”broadly approximate” this interpretation of the folio. Would broad approximation
have been good enough for Galileo? Note that the 116v experiment tests the speed
law in a more effective way. (See the proportion (iv) of Section 3A.)
22
As to 81r, Hill does not think that the middle and outer curves of the diagram
represent actual trajectories. Instead, he argues that the second set of measurements
87
1
2
, 130
1
2
, 177
1
2
, 250 as well as the third 89, 131, 178, 250 are each the horizontal dis-
tances (from the table) of a downward projected ball. In this view, the three trajec-
tories that Galileo considers differ only slightly, with the ball landing at a distance
of 250 punti from the table in each case. Hill summarizes his study of 81r with the
statement ([35, p. 656]) that Galileo
”can conclude that for projections with a fixed baseline value, trajecto-
ries approach semiparabolic status as (or very nearly as) their projec-
tive angles approach the horizontal, just what one would expect if the
parabolic trajectory hypothesis were correct.”
Refer again to the coordinate system discussed in Section 4. The semiparabola that
Hill refers to is the parabolic trajectory through the points (0, 0) and (250, 329.5)
obtained by horizontal projection. Check that its equation is y = 0.005272x
2
.It
follows that this semiparabolic trajectory is 100.3, 141.8, 186.6 and (as we already
know) 250 punti from the table at the respective distances of 53, 106, 183.5, and 329.5
punti below the table top. In terms of the respective horizontal distances, the step
from the first trajectory (this is the inner trajectory corresponding to the data, 81, 121,
170, 250) to the second trajectory (corresponding to the data 87
1
2
, 130
1
2
, 177
1
2
, 250) is
indeed - as Hill asserts - an advance towards the semiparabola just described. Observe,
however, that the second trajectory and the third trajectory (corresponding to the
data 89, 131, 178, 250) are virtually identical. The differences between the respective
horizontal distances - the largest difference is less that 1.5 millimeters - fall well within
the error range already discussed in Section 4. Therefore, the step from the second
trajectory to the third is not an advance towards the semiparabola. So contrary to
Hill’s interpretation, there is no approach to semiparabolic status. Even if Galileo
had carried out the experiment as described, he would only have had very indirect
evidence for the parabolic hypothesis for an oblique trajectory.
In summary, each of the analyses of the experiments of folios 81r and 114v dis-
cussed in this section encounters difficulties. In particular, neither the scenarios of
success that they describe nor the specific information about the experiments that
they provide find support in the evidence supplied by the folios.
7. Conclusions. The role that experiment and measurement have historically played
in the validation of a scientific theory, especially a developing theory, is a subtle
one in general. See Kuhn [21, Chapter 8]. But in the case of folio 116v, we have
seen compelling evidence in Section 3 that this experiment is - in terms of both the
23
validity of the concept and the precision of the execution - a compelling confirmation
of Galileo’s account of motion. This folio refutes the contention of Koyr´e to the effect
that Galileo’s experiments are woefully inadequate. It also confirms that Galileo’s
analyses on day three of the Discorsi as well as the proof on day four of the parabolic
trajectory in the case of a horizontal projection are, at least in a substantial way,
the achievements of Galileo’s work in Padua. Full credit goes to Stillman Drake for
uncovering the meaning of folio 116v and for recognizing its relevance.
While there is consensus in the literature that folio 116v describes a successful
experiment, there is disagreement as to its purpose. Drake and MacLachlan [16] be-
lieve that it is Galileo’s aim to test his principle of horizontal inertia. Most historians
think that Galileo is in pursuit of the time-squared law of fall. See Hill [35, p. 662].
The discussion of Section 3A shows that the experiment tests none of Galileo’s in-
sights independently, but that it in fact tests Galileo’s account of motion as a whole.
Therefore, it tests neither his law of fall nor his principle of inertia directly. Whereas
the test of either the law of fall or the principle of inertia necessarily involves the
measurement of time, the experiment of 116v bypasses any need to measure this elu-
sive variable. This point is of historical significance. The inclined plane experiment
that Galileo describes in the Discorsi is designed to shore up the law of fall and some
of its consequences. (See Proposition II. Theorem II and its Corollaries in [2, pp.
166-171]). It therefore focusses on the connection between distance and time. Settle
[8, p. 21] points out in the context of his reconstruction of this experiment that ”the
measurement of time is the most controversial and the most difficult.” Indeed, it is
the measurement of time that is an explicit target of the skepticism expressed by
Koyr´e (and also Descartes and Mersenne) about Galileo’s experiments with inclined
planes. See [5, pp. 106-107 and 126].
From our modern perspective, 116v is a successful illustration of experiment test-
ing theory. Was Galileo’s perspective the same? What did his experiments mean to
him? Why is there no reference to the folio 116v experiment in the Discorsi? There
have been efforts to answer these questions. In both the Dialogo and the Discorsi
experiments quite clearly serve a didactic even rhetorical function (at least in part)
and Galileo stretches his descriptions of them beyond the limits of his observations.
Naylor [19] discusses the contrast between these descriptions and Galileo’s actual
experimental procedures, and suggests plausibly that ”the problems to be met in
making the folio 116v experiment intelligible for his readers were ... [an] obstacle to
its inclusion in the Discorsi.” Machamer [44] develops the point that for Galileo to
have an intelligible explanation, he needs to have an accompanying experience - often
provided by a mechanical device - that illustrates the phenomenon. In particular,
Machamer regards the idea that Galileo’s insistence on making his thinking about
24
motion intelligible by mechanical models ”fits well” with the practice in geometry
(the mathematical environment in which Galileo worked) of proof by geometrical
construction.
The evident failure of the experiments of folios 81r and 114v does not detract from
the success of 116v. But it does call for a reassesment of Galileo the experimental
scientist. Recall Koyr´e’s assertion ([5, p. 106]) ”Galileo’s experiment is beautifully
conceived; the idea of substituting a body rolling down an inclined plane for a body
in free fall is truly a mark of genius. But, we are obliged to note, its execution is not
of the same order as its conception.” It is indeed the case that Galileo’s experiments
with inclined planes are ingenious in their concept, but rather than their execution,
it is Galileo’s understanding of the underlying physical principles and mathematical
relationships that is not always up to the task.
25
REFERENCES (in chronological order)
For much more extensive bibliographies consult McMullin [9] and Damerow-Freudenthal-
McLaughlin-Renn [38].
1. Galileo Galilei, Dialogo doue ne i congressi di quattro giornate si discorre sopra
i due Massimi Sistemi del Mondo,: Tolemaico, e Copernicano, Florence, 1632.
Stillman Drake translation, Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems
- Ptolemaic and Copernican, University of California Press, 1967.
2. Galileo Galilei, Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche, intorno a due nuove
scienze atteninti alla mecanica & i movimenti locali, Leyden, at the Elzeviers,
1638. H. Crew and A. de Salvio, translation, Dialogues Concerning Two New
Sciences, Northwestern University, Evanston and Chicago, 1950; reprinted by
McGraw Hill, New York, 1963. Stillman Drake translation, Discourses & Math-
ematical Demonstrations Concerning Two New Sciences Pertaining to Mechan-
ics & Local Motion, University of Wisconsin Press, 1974, second edition, Wall
and Thompson, Toronto, 1989.
3. I. Kant, Critik der Reinen Vernunft, B edition 1787. N. K. Smith translation,
Critique of Pure Reason, Second Edition, London, 1956.
4. E. Mach, The Science of Mechanics, Chicago, 1893.
5. A. Koyr´e, Etudes Galil´eennes, Librarie Scientifiques Hermann et Cie, 1939.
John Mepham translation, Galileo Studies, Humanities Press, New Jersey, 1978.
6. A. Koyr´e, An Experiment in Measurement, Proc. Am. Phil. Soc. 97 (1953),
222-237.
7. R. Dugas, Mechanics of the seventeenth century, from the scholastic antecedents
to classical thought, Neuchatel,
`
Editions du Griffon; New York, Central Book
Co., 1958.
8. T. Settle, An Experiment in the History of Science, Science, Vol. 133 (1961),
19-23.
9. E. McMullin, editor, Galileo: Man of Science, New York, NY, Basic Books,
1967.
10. E. McMullin, Galileo: Man of Science, in Galileo: Man of Science, E. McMullin,
editor, 1967, 3-51.
26
11. T. Settle, Galileo’s use of experiment as a tool of investigation, in Galileo: Man
of Science, E. McMullin, editor, 1967, 315-337.
12. S. Drake, Galileo’s Experimental Confirmation of Horizontal Inertia: Unpub-
lished Manuscripts, Isis 64 (1973), 291-305.
13. R. H. Naylor, Galileo and the Problem of Free Fall, The British Journal for the
History of Science 7 (1974), 105-134.
14. R. H. Naylor, The Evolution of an Experiment: Guidobaldo Del Monte and
Galileo’s Discorsi Demonstration of the Parabolic Trajectory, Physis 16 (1974),
323-346.
15. W. L. Wisan, The New Science of Motion: A Study nof Galileo’s De motu
locali, Archive for History of Exact Sciences 13 (1974), 103-306.
16. S. Drake and J. MacLachlan, Galileo’s Discovery of the Parabolic Trajectory,
Scientific American, Vol. 232 (3) (1975), 102-110.
17. W. R. Shea and N. S. Wolf, Stillman Drake and the Archimedean Grandfather
of Experimental Science, Isis 66 (1975), 397-400.
18. R. H. Naylor, Galileo: the Search for the Parabolic Trajectory, Annals of Science
33 (1976), 153-172.
19. R. H. Naylor, Galileo: Real Experiment and Didactic Demonstration, Isis 67
(1976), 398-419.
20. R. H. Naylor, Galileo’s Theory of Motion: Processes of Conceptual Change in
the Period 1604-1610, Annals of Science 34 (1977), 365-392.
21. T. S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension, Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and
Change, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1977.
22. S. Drake, Galileo at Work: His Scientific Biography, The University of Chicago
Press, Chicago and London, 1978.
23. E. McMullin, The Conception of Science in Galileo’s Work, in New Perspectives
on Galileo, R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts, editors, D. Reidel Publishing Company,
Dordrecht, Holland 1978, 209-257.
24. D. Hill, A Note on a Galilean Worksheet, Isis 70 (1979), 269-271.
27
25. R. H. Naylor, The Role of Experiment in Galileo’s Early Work on the Law of
Fall, Annals of Science 37 (1980), 363-378.
26. R. H. Naylor, Galileo’s Theory of Projectile Motion, Isis 71 (1980), 550-570.
27. S. Drake, Analysis of Galileo’s Experimental Data, Annals of Science 39 (1982),
389-397.
28. R. H. Naylor, Galileo’s Early Experiments on Projectile Trajectories, Annals of
Science 40 (1983), 391-394.
29. S. Drake, Comment on Naylor’s ”Galileo’s Early Experiments on Projectile
Trajectories,” Annals of Science 40 (1983), 395.
30. T. Settle, Galileo and Early Experimentation, in Springs of Scientific Creativity.
Essays on founders of Modern Science, R. Aris, H. T. Davis, and R. H. Stuewer,
editors, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis 1983, 3-20.
31. W. L. Wisan, Galileo and the Process of Scientific Creation, Isis 75 (1984),
269-286.
32. S. Drake, Galileo’s Accuracy in Measuring Horizontal Projections, Annali dell’
Instituto e Museo di Storia della Sciencia 10 (1985), 1-14.
33. D. Hill, Galileo’s Work on 116v: A New Analysis, Isis 77 (1986), 283-291.
34. S. A. Bedini, Galileo and Scientific Instrumentation, in Reinterpreting Galileo,
W. A. Wallace, editor, Catholic University of America Press, Washington D.
C., 1986, 127-153.
35. D. Hill, Dissecting Trajectories, Galileo’s Early Experiments on Projectile Mo-
tion and the Law of Free Fall, Isis 79 (1988), 646-668.
36. S. Drake, History of Free Fall, Aristotle to Galileo, Wall & Thompson, Toronto,
1989.
37. S. Drake, Galileo: Pioneer Scientist, University of Toronto Press, 1990.
38. P. Damerow, G. Freudenthal, P. McLaughlin, and J. Renn, Exploring the Limits
of Preclassical Mechanics, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1992.
39. Pope John Paul II, Lessons of the Galileo Case, Origins Vol. 22: No. 22,
November 12, 1992, 369-374.
28
40. Cardinal Paul Poupard, Galileo: Report on Papal Commission Findings, Ori-
gins Vol. 22: No. 22, November 12, 1992, 374-375.
41. D. Hill, Pendulums and Planes: What Galileo didn’t Publish, Nuncius, Vol.
9(2) (1994), 499-515.
42. A. Hahn, Basic Calculus: From Archimedes to Newton to its Role in Science,
Springer-Verlag, New York, 1998.
43. P. Machamer, editor, The Cambridge Companion to Galileo, Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1998.
44. P. Machamer, Galileo’s machines, his mathematics, and his experiments, in The
Cambridge Companion to Galileo, P. Machamer, editor, 53-79.
45. D. Sobel, Galileo’s Daughter, Walker Publishing Company Inc., 1999.
46. Heilbron, The Sun and the Church: Cathedrals As Solar Observatories, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge, MA, 2001.
Department of Mathematics, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN 46556, USA.
29